HORIZONTAL APPLICATION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS – RETHINKING THE…_第1页
HORIZONTAL APPLICATION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS – RETHINKING THE…_第2页
HORIZONTAL APPLICATION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS – RETHINKING THE…_第3页
HORIZONTAL APPLICATION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS – RETHINKING THE…_第4页
HORIZONTAL APPLICATION OF FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS – RETHINKING THE…_第5页
已阅读5页,还剩15页未读 继续免费阅读

下载本文档

版权说明:本文档由用户提供并上传,收益归属内容提供方,若内容存在侵权,请进行举报或认领

文档简介

1、horizontal application of fundamental rights rethinking the structures of constitutional democracyjohan van der walt* professor of law, university of glasgow.“entscheidend ging es jedoch sowohl der dclaration als auch der deutschen grundrechtsdoktrin darum, da es der staat, vor allem der gesetzgeber

2、, war, der die freiheitssphre auch im privaten recht zu sichern hatte.” klaus stern staatsrecht iii/1, 1516.i introductionvolume iii/1 of klaus sterns staatsrecht der bundesrepublik deutschland introduced me to german drittwirkung or horizontal application jurisprudence. it is in this volume of ster

3、ns monumental work on german public law that i read in 1999, as a humboldt scholar under klaus sterns hospitable betreuung, that the horizontal application of fundamental rights or drittwirkung der grundrechte always confronts the judiciary with the problem of two competing or conflicting fundamenta

4、l rights. when one party in a private legal conflict deems it fit to articulate a legal claim in terms of a fundamental right, the other party will invariably be able to do the same. stern puts the matter as follows:“die besonderheit dieser konstellation liegt darin, da hier die privatrechtssubjekte

5、 prinzipiell beide grundrechtsberechtigte sind; entfalten in diesem verhltnis die grundrechte wirkungen derart, da hierdurch der eine gegenber dem anderen beteiligten geschtzt wird, so kann dies zugleich eine beeintrchtigung der grundrechtlichen freiheit des anderen beteiligten privatrechtssubjekts

6、bedeuten. die grundrechte wrden daher in diesen verhltnissen fr alle beteiligten gleichzeitigt zu rechten und zu pflichten fhren.” klaus stern, staatsrecht iii/1 (mnchen, c h beck, 1988) 1513.“the specificity of this constellation lies in the fact that the private law subjects involved in the disput

7、e are in principle both bearers of fundamental rights; when the fundamental rights relationship between the parties is such that the one partys fundamental rights are protected against the other, the other can also claim that such protection would, in turn, abridge his fundamental rights. the fundam

8、ental rights would therefore in this case imply rights and duties for all parties involved.”the conflict of fundamental rights that stern describes here portrays a structural complexity at the heart of horizontal application jurisprudence. one of the dexterous ways by which legal theory has all alon

9、g sought to sidestep this complexity was to deny that horizontal application involves a clash of fundamental rights in the way stern describes it in this passage. in german literature it was especially jrgen schwabe who insisted persuasively on the “so-called” or “sogenannte” status of horizontal ap

10、plication. horizontal application, according to schwabe, was a non-issue or pseudo-problem; in the final analysis it is always the state and not the private individual that is the real object of constitutional review. jrgen schwabe, die sogennante drittwirkung der grundrechte. zur einwirkung der gru

11、ndrechte auf den privatrechtsverkehr (mnchen, wilhelm goldmann, 1971) 9-25. schwabes view can be said to have triumphed in the jurisprudence of the german federal constitutional court (bundesverfassungsgericht, hereafter referred to as the gfcc) when the gfcc commenced to emphasise the duty of the s

12、tate to protect and guarantee the fundamental rights of citizens as the heart of its “horizontal application” jurisprudence. 39 bverfge 1; 46 bverfge 116; 49 bverfge 89; 77 bverfge 381; 88 bverfge 205; 96 bverfge 56.and strictly speaking, the view that it is always the state and never the individual

13、 that figures as the object of constitutional review, was all along quite evidently already embodied in the epochal lth case which precipitated the gfccs horizontal application jurisprudence in 1957. already in lth does one encounter the crucial formula that the gfcc would use almost invariably in i

14、ts later judgments. it is not the individual that abridged the right of the constitutional plaintiff (verfassungsbeschwerde), but the trial court that failed to interpret and assess his fundamental rights correctly. this is the way the gfcc phrased the matter in lth:“das bundesverfassungsgericht ist

15、 auf grund dieser erwgungen zu der berzeugung gelangt, da das landgericht bei seiner beurteilung des verhaltens des beschwerdefhrers die besondere bedeutung verkannt hat, die dem grundrecht auf freie meinungsuerung auch dort zukommt, wo es mit privaten interessen anderer in konflikt tritt. das urtei

16、l des landgerichts beruht auf diesem verfehlen grundrechtlicher mastbe und verletzt so das grundrecht des beschwerdefhrers aus art 5 abs 1 satz 1 gg.” 7 bverfge 198, 230 emphasis added. the court relied on this wording again and again in subsequent judgments. see 24 bverfge 278; 25 bverfge 256; 30 b

17、verfge 173; 34 bverfge 35 bverfge 202; 42 bverfge 142; 46 bverfge 325; 54 bverfge 129; 54 bverfge 148; 60 bverfge 234; 61 bverfge 1; 62 bverfge 230; 66 bverfge 116; 73 bverfge 261.“the decision of the regional court failed to recognise the significance which the right to freedom of expression enjoys

18、 also in those cases where it comes into conflict with private interests. as such it fell short of constitutional criteria and must be deemed to have violated the fundamental right which the plaintiff enjoys in terms of article 5 i.”considering the schutzpflicht jurisprudence of the gfcc and this fo

19、rmula that it coined in lth, schwabe would appear to be correct. ultimately it is always the state, some state action or ommission, that constitutes the object of constitutional review, also when the conflict that necessitated the review has its origins in private legal relationships. this concessio

20、n to schwabe does nevertheless not mean that sterns asessment of drittwirkung in terms of a conflict between fundamental rights is incorrect. one of the points that i will be stressing in this essay is that stern is in fact correct, but at a much more fundamental and somewhat different way than is a

21、pparent at first glance. the special nature (besonderheit) of drittwirkung, i shall argue, consists in the way it reminds us that all constitutional review concerns a conflict between two fundamental rights. and this reminder, i shall argue further, is a crucial point of entry for a much needed reth

22、inking of the fundamental structure of constitutional democracy in the era of increasing supra-statal governance evident in contemporary europe and elsewhere in the globalised world. and sterns view regarding a conflict of fundamental rights, we shall see, goes to the heart of the structure that is

23、at issue here. my argument will proceed in four steps. section ii will briefly expound an analysis of american state action jurisprudence. the point of this exposition will be to point out the close correspondence between schwabes state oriented approach to drittwrikung and the state action jurispru

24、dence of both the united states supreme court and prominent american legal theorists. section iii will contrast the state oriented understanding of constitutional review evident in the state action doctrine with the significantly different understanding of “constitutional review” prevalent in france

25、, in terms of which the state is the subject and not the object of constitutional review. this contrasting comparison between american and french constitutional theory and practice will serve as a hermeneutic background for an engagement with a crucial point that walter leisner made in his epochal c

26、ontribution to the german drittwirkung debate. leisner, grundrechte und privatrecht (mnchen, c.h. beck, 1960). as will become clear towards the end of section iii, leisner espoused a typically french understanding of “constitutional review” in terms of which the state is not the primary suspect of c

27、onstitutional transgressions, but quite to the contrary, the primary guarantor of the constitution and constitutional rights. leisner forwarded this view to make a crucial point in his theoretical analysis of the drittwirkung problematic: constitutional review is primarily concerned with the review

28、of private power, and not just anomalously, secondarily or indirectly so, as drittwirkung jurisprudence has pervasively come to maintain in the wake of jellineks emphasis of the staatsrichtung of constitutional review. leisner, we shall see, quite evidently viewed private power, not public power, as

29、 the primary threat to constitutional rights. the view of the state as the primary guarantor of constitutional rights instead of the primary suspect of constitutional violations can be argued to have gained new significance in the wake of the gfccs lisbon judgment in 2009. that private power and the

30、 subversion of public power by supra-statal governance have come to constitute more significant threats to constitutional rights than state conduct in the era of globalisation, has been observed by many european legal theorists in the wake of the viking, laval, luxembourg and rffert judgements of th

31、e european court of justice (ecj) in recent years. section iv engages with the positions taken by the gfcc and ecj in these cases against the background of the arguments developed in sections i to iii.section v concludes this essay with a number of reflections on how one might reconceive constitutio

32、nal democracy in view of insights gained from sections i to iv. what this essay as a whole hopes to convey with the thoughts developed in sections i to v can provisionally be summarised as follows: the drittwirkung question invites legal theory to return to and rethink the original raison dtre of th

33、e constitutional state in a time that has largely come to forget and suppress this raison dtre. the result of this suppression and forgetfulness is unsurprising. we live in a time of rampant private freedoms, glaring inequalities, and indistinct private/public modes of governance that threaten to di

34、splace public spheres and democratic accountability in just about all walks of life. the banking industry has in recent months and years come to demand entitlement to unimaginable sums of public money simply because they are “to big too fall”. this is a startling example, but just one of many that r

35、eveal the extent to which the power of contemporary constitutional democracies have come to be displaced by conglomerates of power that increasingly render the public-private distinction meaningless. this development may well be signalling the emergence of forms of power akin to pre-modern feudal po

36、wers that united the capacities of dominium and imperium. this is a point that legal theorists must ponder incisively today. a radical reflection on drittwirkung, the state action doctrine or the horizontal application of constitutional rights provides legal theory with a crucial opportunity to do s

37、o.ii the american state action doctrinethe american state action doctrine has its origin in a dictum of justice bradley in the majority opinion of the court in the civil rights cases. this is how justice bradley put the matter:“in this connection, it is proper to state that civil rights, such as are

38、 guaranteed by the constitution against state aggression, cannot be impaired by the wrongful acts of individuals, unsupported by the state authority in the shape of laws, customs, or judicial or executive proceedings. the wrongful act of an individual, unsupported by any such authority, is simply a

39、private wrong, or a crime of that individual; an invasion of the rights of the injured party, it is true, whether they affect his person, his property, or his reputation; but if not sanctioned in some way by the state, or not done under the state authority, his rights remain in full force, and may p

40、resumably be vindicated by resort to the laws of the state for redress. hence, in all those cases where the constitution seeks to protect the rights of the citizen against discriminative and unjust laws of the state by prohibiting such laws, it is not individual offences, but abrogation and denial o

41、f rights, which it denounces and for which it clothes the congress with power to provide a remedy. this abrogation and denial of rights for which the states alone were or could be responsible was the great seminal and fundamental wrong which was intended to be remedied. and the remedy to be provided

42、 must necessarily be predicated upon that wrong. it must assume that, in the cases provided for, the evil or wrong actually committed rests upon some state law or state authority for its excuse and perpetration.” 109 u.s. 3 (1883) at 17.the reasoning embodied in this dictum enabled the united states

43、 supreme court to develop an extensive jurisprudence according to which it was constitutionally unobjectionable for private individuals to discriminate against others on the basis of race; hence charles blacks famous description of the state action doctrine as “the last unexpunged clause of americas

44、 long settled gentlemans agreement about racism”. charles black jr. “state action, equal protection, and californias proposition 14” (1967) 81 harvard law review 79, 109. this gentlemans agreement, however, no longer seemed so gentlemanly when the supreme court had to decide the epochal case of shel

45、ley v kraemer in 1948, and the court did its best to break out of it. the disputes in shelley turned on the question whether the judicial enforcement of restrictive covenants between private individuals constituted missouri state action that was subject to review in terms of the 14th amendment of th

46、e united states constitution. the court decided that it did, thereby exploding the state action doctrine. if judicial enforcement constitutes state action, the existence or non-existence of state action can no longer be an interesting or significant question for the judiciary to consider, for this v

47、ery consideration would as such already constitute state action. had shelley remained good law in all respects, it surely would have terminated the state action doctrine, but the supreme court subsequently restricted shelleys applicability severely enough to keep or restore americas “gentlemans agre

48、ement”, irrespective of how unsavoury this agreement had become for many. the explosion of the state action doctrine in shelley could have been a watershed moment in american law, but it turned out to be nothing but a momentary hiccup, as will soon become clear. shelley was not the only case that ca

49、n be said to have exploded, albeit again only momentarily, the state action doctrine. two other supreme court cases are also noteworthy in this respect, the most prominent of which is the 1963 case of new york times v sullivan. 376 us 254 (1963). in sullivan, justice brennan accepted without much ad

50、o that defamation law embodied in the common law of the state of alabama constitutes state action for purposes of the 14th amendment. and justice frankfurter already decided in the 1941 case of labour v swing that common law rules regarding unlawful picketing constituted state action under the 14th

51、amendment. 312 us 321 (1941). sullivan and swing are very similar as far as their acceptance of common law as a form of state action is concerned, but sullivan would come to strike american legal theory as the pivotal case. state action should have been duly considered to be “out of business” after

52、new york times v sullivan, frank michelman observes. if the constitution tolerates neither executive state administration, nor state legislation, nor state common law that falls foul of its guarantees, there is simply no basis left on which any judicial decision can escape state action review in ter

53、ms of the 14th amendment. yet, anyone who knows something about american law, also knows, contends michelman further, “something persists in american jurisprudence that walks and talks like a state action doctrine with teeth.” michelman “the bill of rights, the common law, and the freedom-friendly s

54、tate” (2003) 58 university of miami law review 401, at 404. how did this persistence of the state action doctrine come about? the answer is simple. the american judiciary simply chose to ignore the irrefutable logic of shelley, swing and sullivan. this logic was eminently clear to former chief justi

55、ce rehnquist in flagg brothers, inc. v brooks, 436 u.s. 149 (1978), hereafter cited as flagg brothers.but “he insisted that american constitutional legal doctrine must pretend not to notice it, as michelman explains elsewhere. michelman “w(h)ither the constitution?” 2000 (21) cardozo lr, 1063, 1076.

56、 rehnquist simply stated dead pan that “it would intolerably broaden . . . the notion of state action under the fourteenth amendment to hold that the mere existence of a body of property law in a state, whether decisional or statutory, itself amounted to state action. . . .” flagg brothers at 160 n.

57、10. canaris can be said to have rallied to a “rehnquist call” in germany, claus-wilhelm canaris “grundrechte und privatrecht” (1984) 184 archiv fr die zivilistische praxis 201, 219: “es bleibt allenfalls noch das argument, im zwangvolstrekkungsverfahren greife der staat selbst ein. auch das berzeugt

58、 jedoch nicht. denn die vollstrekkung eines auf verfassungsgemen normen beruhenden zivilurteils stellt als solche keine eigenstndige grundrechtseinschrnkung dar.” the reworked essay of 1999, grundrechte und privatrecht: eine zwischenbilanz (berlin/ new york: walter de gruyter) does not make this poi

59、nt as expressly. but a significant contingent of american legal theorists have all along refused to entertain the kind of pretence for which justice rehnquist (as he was at the time) called in 1978 and they continued to do so thereafter. they all basically endorsed the schwabian point that no lawful individual action can be claimed not to involve some or other form of state involvem

温馨提示

  • 1. 本站所有资源如无特殊说明,都需要本地电脑安装OFFICE2007和PDF阅读器。图纸软件为CAD,CAXA,PROE,UG,SolidWorks等.压缩文件请下载最新的WinRAR软件解压。
  • 2. 本站的文档不包含任何第三方提供的附件图纸等,如果需要附件,请联系上传者。文件的所有权益归上传用户所有。
  • 3. 本站RAR压缩包中若带图纸,网页内容里面会有图纸预览,若没有图纸预览就没有图纸。
  • 4. 未经权益所有人同意不得将文件中的内容挪作商业或盈利用途。
  • 5. 人人文库网仅提供信息存储空间,仅对用户上传内容的表现方式做保护处理,对用户上传分享的文档内容本身不做任何修改或编辑,并不能对任何下载内容负责。
  • 6. 下载文件中如有侵权或不适当内容,请与我们联系,我们立即纠正。
  • 7. 本站不保证下载资源的准确性、安全性和完整性, 同时也不承担用户因使用这些下载资源对自己和他人造成任何形式的伤害或损失。

评论

0/150

提交评论